The decay of the natural ground for the family relationships was largely unanticipated and unprepared for in the early modern thinkers. But they did suggest a certain reform of the family, reflecting the movement away from the constraints of duty, toward reliance on those elements of the family that could be understood to flow out of free expressions of personal sentiment. In Locke, paternal authority is turned into parental authority, a rejection of a father’s divine or natural right to rule and to rule permanently, in favor of a father’s and a mother’s right to care for their children as long as they need care, for the sake of the children’s freedom—which the child will immediately recognize, when he reaches majority, to have been for his own benefit. There is nothing left of the reverence toward the father as the symbol of the divine on earth, the unquestioned bearer of authority. Rather, sons and daughters will calculate that they have benefited from their parents’ care, which prepared them for the freedom they enjoy, and they will be grateful, although they have no reciprocal duty, except insofar as they wish to leave behind a plausible model for the conduct of their own children toward them. They may, if they please, obey their father in order to inherit his estate, if he has one, which he can dispose of as he pleases. From the point of view of the children, the family retains its validity on the basis of modern principles, and Locke prepares the way for the democratic family, so movingly described by Tocqueville in Democracy in America.
So far, so good. The children are reconciled to the family. But the problem, it seems to me, is in the motive of the parents to care for their children. The children can say to their parents: “You are strong, and we are weak. Use your strength to help us. You are rich, and we are poor. Spend your money on us. You are wise, and we are ignorant. Teach us.” But why should mother and father want to do so much, involving so much sacrifice without any reward? Perhaps parental care is a duty, or family life has great joys. But neither of these is a conclusive reason when rights and individual autonomy hold sway. The children have unconditional need for and receive unquestionable benefits from the parents; the same cannot be asserted about parents.
Locke believed, and the events of our time seem to confirm his belief, that women have an instinctive attachment to children that cannot be explained as self-interest or calculation. The attachment of mother and child is perhaps the only undeniable natural social bond. It is not always effective, and it can, with effort, be suppressed, but it is always a force. And this is what we see today. But what about the father? Maybe he loves imagining his own eternity through the generations stemming from him. But this is only an act of imagination, one that can be attenuated by other concerns and calculations, as well as by his losing faith in the continuation of his name for very long in the shifting conditions of democracy. Of necessity, therefore, it was understood to be the woman’s job to get and hold the man by her charms and wiles because, by nature, nothing else would induce him to give up his freedom in favor of the heavy duties of family. But women no longer wish to do this, and they, with justice, consider it unfair according to the principles governing us. So the cement that bound the family together crumbled. It is not the children who break away; it is the parents who abandon them. Women are no longer willing to make unconditional and perpetual commitments on unequal terms, and, no matter what they hope, nothing can effectively make most men share equally the responsibilities of childbearing and childrearing. The divorce rate is only the most striking symptom of this breakdown.
None of this results from the sixties, or from the appeal to masculine vanity begun by advertisers in the fifties, or from any other superficial, pop culture events. More than two hundred years ago Rousseau saw with alarm the seeds of the breakdown of the family in liberal society, and he dedicated much of his genius to trying to correct it. He found that the critical connection between man and woman was being broken by individualism, and focused his efforts, theoretical and practical, on encouraging passionate romantic love in them. He wanted to rebuild and reinforce that connection, previously encumbered by now discredited religious and civil regulation, on modern grounds of desire and consent. He retraced the picture of nature that had become a palimpsest under the abrasion of modern criticism, and he enticed men and women into admiring its teleological ordering, specifically the complementarity between the two sexes, which mesh and set the machine of life in motion, each differing from and needing the other, from the depths of the body to the heights of the soul. He set utter abandon to the sentiments and imaginations of idealized love against calculation of individual interest. Rousseau inspired a whole genre of novelistic and poetic literature that lived feverishly for over a century, coexisting with the writings of the Benthams and the Mills who were earnestly at work homogenizing the sexes. His undertaking had the heaviest significance because human community was at risk. In essence he was persuading women freely to be different from men and to take on the burden of entering a positive contract with the family, as opposed to a negative, individual, self-protective contract with the state. Tocqueville picked up this theme and described the absolute differentiation of husband’s and wife’s functions and ways of life in the American family. This he contrasted to the disorder, nay, chaos, of Europe, which he attributed to a misunderstanding or misapplication of the principle of equality—only an abstraction when not informed by nature’s imperatives.
1. In family relations, parental authority should take the place of paternal authority.
2. Leaving no reverence toward the father as the unquestioned bearer of authority is a right thing.
3. The children have unconditional need for and receive unquestionable benefits from the parents.
4. The attachment of mother and child is perhaps the only undeniable natural social bond.
5. To get married and become a parent means to give up his/her freedom in favor of the heavy duties of family.
6. The critical connection between man and woman is being broken by individualism.
7. Women should be different from men and take on the burden of entering a positive contract with the family, as opposed to a negative, individual, self-protective contract with the state.
本文选自
《美国国情:美国社会与文化(第3版)》
常俊跃 李莉莉 赵永青 主编
ISBN:978-7-301-32331-1
定价:49元
拓展阅读
21世纪内容语言融合(CLI)系列英语教材是在CLI教育理念指导下,基于国家社会科学基金项目“英语专业基础阶段内容依托式课程改革研究”推出的系列英语内容依托教材。适用于英语专业一、二年级的学生,也适用于具有中学英语基础的非英语专业学生和英语爱好者学习。本套教材具有以下主要特色:
--遵循了全新的教学理念,社会文化内容与语言技能并重;
--涉及了丰富的教学内容,培养学生对不同社会文化的敏感性;
--引进了真实的教学材料,表现手法活泼,效果直观生动;
--设计了新颖的教材板块,结构安排系统合理,突出学生的主体地位;
--提供了多样的活动训练,培养学生综合运用语言和知识进行沟通的能力和逻辑思维能力;
--推荐了经典的学习材料,延伸课堂教学,激发生术的学习热情。
美国国情:美国社会与文化(第3版)
常俊跃 李莉莉 赵永青 主编
ISBN:978-7-301-32331-1
定价:49元
美国国情:美国历史文化(第2版)
常俊跃 夏洋 赵永青 主编
定价:43.00
978-7-301-27129-2
美国国情:美国自然人文地理(第2版)
常俊跃 赵秀艳 赵永青 主编
定价:39.00
978-7-301-27111-7
英国国情:英国社会与文化(第2版)
常俊跃 李莉莉 赵永青 主编
定价:37.00
978-7-301-27439-2
英国国情:英国历史文化(第2版)
常俊跃 夏洋 赵永青 主编
定价:45.00
978-7-301-27166-7
英国国情:英国自然人文地理(第2版)
常俊跃 赵秀艳 赵永青 主编
定价:39.00
978-7-301-27081-3
欧洲文化入门(第2版)
常俊跃 黄洁芳 赵永青 主编
ISBN: 978-7-301-31591-0
定价:49元
澳新加社会文化
常俊跃 高璐璐 赵永青 主编
定价:29.00
978-7-301-18831-6
中国文化(英文版)(第2版)
常俊跃 霍跃红 王焱 赵永青 主编
定价:37.00
978-7-301-27427-9
跨文化交际(第2版)
常俊跃 吕春媚 赵永青 主编
ISBN: 978-7-301-32601-5
定价:49元
古希腊罗马神话
杨俊峰 黄洁芳 常俊跃 主编
定价:36.00
978-7-301-21775-7
圣经与文化
常俊跃 李文萍 赵永青 主编
定价:30.00
978-7-301-19224-5
英语词汇学教程
夏洋 邵林 主编
定价:38.00
978-7-301-28218-2
语用学教程
刘风光 王澍 于秀成 姜晖 主编
定价:38.00
978-7-301-29518-2
北大外文学堂(pupwaiwen)
如果您对文章感兴趣,请长按左侧二维码关注“北大外文学堂”,我们会为您提供最优质的内容和服务。快和我们互动吧。
点击“阅读原文”带走这本好书^_^